Araştırma Makalesi
BibTex RIS Kaynak Göster

Reviewing the Extended Mind Theory: Theoretical Insights and the Role of Experimental Philosophy in Understanding Cognitive Boundaries

Yıl 2025, Cilt: 8 Sayı: 1, 1 - 24, 30.06.2025
https://doi.org/10.51404/metazihin.1692629

Öz

This study proposes a theoretical account of the evolution of the extended mind hypothesis by using experimental philosophy (x-phi) in the study of the concept of intrinsic content. Building on Clark's (1998) argument on behalf of extended cognition and Adams and Aizawa's (2001) neural-centric process argument, it considers how cognitive boundary judgments relying on intuition can illuminate the use of external devices, such as notebooks or mobile phones, in mental processes. The study concludes that x-phi's methods, which explore folk intuitions, offer a practical means of figuring out whether intrinsic content is contained in the brain or distributed across external systems. By considering factors like socioeconomic status that may affect intuitions, it highlights x-phi's ability to provide empirical insights to discussions in philosophy of mind (Knobe & Nichols, 2008). Drawing on inter-disciplinary methods across several disciplines (Yüksel, 2021), this research links philosophy and cognitive science and offers an addition to debates around 4E cognition (embodied, embedded, extended, enactive). The proposed method is aimed at making the theoretical and intuitive components of extended mind theory more transparent and providing a gateway towards future empirical investigations.

Kaynakça

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). “The bounds of cognition.” Philosophical Psychology, 14(1): 43–64. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515080120033571
  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2010). “Defending the bounds of cognition.” In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 67–80). MIT Press.
  • Alexander, J., Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. M. (2010). “Accentuate the negative: The positive results of negative methodology.” Philosophical Psychology, 23(2): 141–164. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515081003625286
  • Bourdieu, P. (1986). “The forms of capital.” In J. Richardson (Ed.), Handbook of theory and research for the sociology of education (pp. 241–258). Greenwood.
  • Burge, T. (1986). “Individualism and psychology.” The Philosophical Review, 95(1): 3–45. https://doi.org/10.2307/2185129
  • Clark, A. (2005). “Intrinsic content, active memory and the extended mind.” Analysis, 65(1): 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/65.1.1
  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press.
  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (2010). “The extended mind.” In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 27–42). MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. MIT Press.
  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.
  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. MIT Press.
  • Kirsh, D. (2010). “Thinking with external representations.” AI & Society, 25(4): 441–454. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-010-0272-8
  • Knobe, J. (2007). “Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance.” Philosophical Explorations, 10(2): 119–121. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869790701305905
  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2008). “An experimental philosophy manifesto.” In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy (pp. 3–14). Oxford University Press.
  • Lau, J., & Deutsch, M. (2014). “Externalism about mental content.” In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 ed.). Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/content-externalism/
  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2004). “Semantics, cross-cultural style.” Cognition, 92(3): B1–B12. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2003.10.003
  • Menary, R. (2006). “Attacking the bounds of cognition.” Philosophical Psychology, 19(3): 329–344. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515080600690557
  • Nagel, J. (2012). “Intuitions and experiments: A defense of the case method in epistemology.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(3): 495–527. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00634.x
  • Newen, A., De Bruin, L., & Gallagher, S. (2018). The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition. Oxford University Press.
  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). “Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions.” Noûs, 41(4): 663–685. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00666.x
  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. MIT Press.
  • Sosa, E. (2007). “Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuition.” Philosophical Studies, 132(1): 99–107. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9050-3
  • Sripada, C., & Stich, S. (2006). “A framework for the psychology of norms.” In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind: Culture and cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 280–301). Oxford University Press.
  • Sterelny, K. (2010). “Minds: Extended or scaffolded?” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4): 465–481. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9174-y
  • Stich, S. P., & Tobia, K. (2016). “Experimental philosophy’s challenge to the ‘great tradition’.” Analytic Philosophy, 57(4): 282–299. https://doi.org/10.1111/phib.12098
  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.
  • Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2001). “Normativity and epistemic intuitions.” Philosophical Topics, 29(1/2): 429–460. https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics2001291/217
  • Yüksel, N. (2021). “Do epistemic intuitions vary across actors? A mixed-methods study of philosophers’ and non-philosophers’ knowledge attributions” [Unpublished doctoral dissertation]. University of Exeter.
  • Yüksel, N. (2023). “A New Movement in the Philosophical Tradition: Experimental Philosophy” Felsefe Arkivi, 59: 43–55. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1302607

Genişletilmiş Zihin Kuramı Üzerine: Bilişsel Sınırları Anlamada Kuramsal Yaklaşımlar ve Deneysel Felsefenin Rolü

Yıl 2025, Cilt: 8 Sayı: 1, 1 - 24, 30.06.2025
https://doi.org/10.51404/metazihin.1692629

Öz

Bu çalışma, içsel içerik (intrinsic content) kavramının araştırılmasında deneysel felsefe (experimental philosophy/x-phi) yöntemlerinden yararlanarak, genişletilmiş zihin teorisinin (extended mind theory) kuramsal gelişimine yönelik bir değerlendirme sunmaktadır. Bu çalışmada, Clark’ın (1998) genişletilmiş biliş (extended cognition) yaklaşımı ile Adams ve Aizawa’nın (2001) sinir-merkezli süreç (neural-centric process) savı temel alınarak, bireylerin dışsal araçlar—örneğin cep telefonları ya da not defterleri—ile zihinsel süreçleri ilişkilendirme biçimleri, verdikleri felsefi yargılar (philosophical judgments) üzerinden ele alınmaktadır. Araştırma, felsefi yargılara odaklanan deneysel felsefe yöntemlerinin, içsel içeriğin yalnızca beyin merkezli (brain-centred) olarak mı bulunduğunu yoksa zihinden dış dünyaya aktarılarak mı dağıldığını (distributed) anlamanın işlevsel bir araç sunduğunu öne sürmektedir. Ayrıca, bu tür felsefi yargıları etkileyebilecek sosyo-ekonomik durum (socioeconomic status) gibi etmenler göz önünde bulundurularak, deneysel felsefenin zihin felsefesi tartışmalara ampirik katkı sağlayabileceği vurgulanmaktadır (Knobe & Nichols, 2008). Disiplinlerarası yöntemlerden (Yüksel, 2021) yararlanan bu araştırma, felsefe ile bilişsel arasında bir köprü kurmakta ve 4E biliş (4E cognition-embodied: bedenlenmiş, embedded: gömülü, extended: genişletilmiş, enactive: etkin/edimsel) çerçevesindeki tartışmalara katkı sunmaktadır. Önerilen yöntem, genişletilmiş zihin teorisinin hem kuramsal boyutlarını hem de felsefi yargıya dayalı yönlerini daha görünür kılmayı ve ileride gerçekleştirilecek ampirik araştırmalar için bir temel oluşturmayı amaçlamaktadır.

Kaynakça

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). “The bounds of cognition.” Philosophical Psychology, 14(1): 43–64. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515080120033571
  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2010). “Defending the bounds of cognition.” In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 67–80). MIT Press.
  • Alexander, J., Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. M. (2010). “Accentuate the negative: The positive results of negative methodology.” Philosophical Psychology, 23(2): 141–164. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515081003625286
  • Bourdieu, P. (1986). “The forms of capital.” In J. Richardson (Ed.), Handbook of theory and research for the sociology of education (pp. 241–258). Greenwood.
  • Burge, T. (1986). “Individualism and psychology.” The Philosophical Review, 95(1): 3–45. https://doi.org/10.2307/2185129
  • Clark, A. (2005). “Intrinsic content, active memory and the extended mind.” Analysis, 65(1): 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/65.1.1
  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press.
  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (2010). “The extended mind.” In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 27–42). MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. MIT Press.
  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.
  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. MIT Press.
  • Kirsh, D. (2010). “Thinking with external representations.” AI & Society, 25(4): 441–454. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-010-0272-8
  • Knobe, J. (2007). “Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance.” Philosophical Explorations, 10(2): 119–121. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869790701305905
  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2008). “An experimental philosophy manifesto.” In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy (pp. 3–14). Oxford University Press.
  • Lau, J., & Deutsch, M. (2014). “Externalism about mental content.” In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 ed.). Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/content-externalism/
  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2004). “Semantics, cross-cultural style.” Cognition, 92(3): B1–B12. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2003.10.003
  • Menary, R. (2006). “Attacking the bounds of cognition.” Philosophical Psychology, 19(3): 329–344. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515080600690557
  • Nagel, J. (2012). “Intuitions and experiments: A defense of the case method in epistemology.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(3): 495–527. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00634.x
  • Newen, A., De Bruin, L., & Gallagher, S. (2018). The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition. Oxford University Press.
  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). “Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions.” Noûs, 41(4): 663–685. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00666.x
  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. MIT Press.
  • Sosa, E. (2007). “Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuition.” Philosophical Studies, 132(1): 99–107. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9050-3
  • Sripada, C., & Stich, S. (2006). “A framework for the psychology of norms.” In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind: Culture and cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 280–301). Oxford University Press.
  • Sterelny, K. (2010). “Minds: Extended or scaffolded?” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4): 465–481. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9174-y
  • Stich, S. P., & Tobia, K. (2016). “Experimental philosophy’s challenge to the ‘great tradition’.” Analytic Philosophy, 57(4): 282–299. https://doi.org/10.1111/phib.12098
  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.
  • Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2001). “Normativity and epistemic intuitions.” Philosophical Topics, 29(1/2): 429–460. https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics2001291/217
  • Yüksel, N. (2021). “Do epistemic intuitions vary across actors? A mixed-methods study of philosophers’ and non-philosophers’ knowledge attributions” [Unpublished doctoral dissertation]. University of Exeter.
  • Yüksel, N. (2023). “A New Movement in the Philosophical Tradition: Experimental Philosophy” Felsefe Arkivi, 59: 43–55. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1302607
Toplam 29 adet kaynakça vardır.

Ayrıntılar

Birincil Dil İngilizce
Konular Zihin Felsefesi, Yapay Zekâ Felsefesi
Bölüm Araştırma/İnceleme Makaleleri
Yazarlar

Necmıye Yuksel 0000-0003-2594-8773

Yayımlanma Tarihi 30 Haziran 2025
Gönderilme Tarihi 9 Mayıs 2025
Kabul Tarihi 30 Haziran 2025
Yayımlandığı Sayı Yıl 2025 Cilt: 8 Sayı: 1

Kaynak Göster

APA Yuksel, N. (2025). Reviewing the Extended Mind Theory: Theoretical Insights and the Role of Experimental Philosophy in Understanding Cognitive Boundaries. MetaZihin: Yapay Zeka ve Zihin Felsefesi Dergisi, 8(1), 1-24. https://doi.org/10.51404/metazihin.1692629